|
|
Papers from the Colloquium
Theme 4: Evidence and Context
Dr Jason Davies, UCL
Herodotus, the father of history, tells us that:
Now the Egyptians, before the reign of their king Psammetichus,
believed themselves to be the most ancient of mankind. Since
Psammetichus, however, made an attempt to discover who were actually
the primitive race, they have been of opinion that while they
surpass all other nations, the Phrygians surpass them in antiquity.
This king, finding it impossible to make out by dint of inquiry
what men were the most ancient, contrived the following method
of discovery:- He took two children of the common sort, and gave
them over to a herdsman to bring up at his folds, strictly charging
him to let no one utter a word in their presence, but to keep
them in a sequestered cottage, and from time to time introduce
goats to their apartment, see that they got their fill of milk,
and in all other respects look after them. His object herein
was to know, after the indistinct babblings of infancy were over,
what word they would first articulate. It happened as he had
anticipated. The herdsman obeyed his orders for two years, and
at the end of that time, on his one day opening the door of their
room and going in, the children both ran up to him with outstretched
arms, and distinctly said "Becos." When this first
happened the herdsman took no notice; but afterwards when he
observed, on coming often to see after them, that the word was
constantly in their mouths, he informed his lord, and by his
command brought the children into his presence. Psammetichus
then himself heard them say the word, upon which he proceeded
to make inquiry what people there was who called anything "becos,"
and hereupon he learnt that "becos" was the Phrygian
name for bread. In consideration of this circumstance the Egyptians
yielded their claims, and admitted the greater antiquity of the
Phrygians. That these were the real facts I learnt at Memphis from
the priests of Vulcan. The Greeks, among other foolish tales, relate
that Psammetichus had the children brought up by women whose tongues
he had previously cut out; but the priests said their bringing
up was such as I have stated above. I got much other information
also from conversation with these priests while I was at Memphis,
and I even went to Heliopolis and to Thebes, expressly to try whether
the priests of those places would agree in their accounts with
the priests at Memphis.
Nowadays of course no-one would dream of doing this: one would
have to use animals in such an experiment.
We could do an awful lot with this example: obviously the experiment
appears somewhat naive to us. But, though I confess I used the
story to get your attention and possibly a laugh, we can use moments
such as these to indicate just how huge the transitions have been
in the last 2,500 years or so. It is not just that we would use
different methods: the entire enquiry is meaningless to us. Language
is not just a question of vocabulary, as every language student
discovers to their horror: it is as much about syntax; nor do we
consider that it is some primeval given, overridden by obscure
cultural forces to produce other languages. Actually, and you could
not possibly know this unless you had read Herodotus with some
care, it is the importance of language as an index of culture,
civilisation and insight that has changed; and the authority of
antiquity, chronological pre-eminence, is almost reversed in a
world where the real truth is round the corner and 'old' knowledge
is almost certainly useless. What would now at best be considered
an item of curiosity was then a hugely important social and political
factor.
What first appeared to be a scientific transition actually turned
out to be an historical transition: what appeared to be a (proto-)
scientific concern was what we would call a cultural issue. The
kind of questions being asked were determined not by some undefined
and normalised human curiosity but were culturally defined.
You can see the beginning of a discussion here about the value
of the history of science: studying history gives a far longer
perspective than studying contemporary and can throw unexpected
light on our assumptions. We generally assume we are more advanced
than previous societies by virtue of our technological achievements:
the desirability of ever faster, more powerful gadgets is not questioned,
except by a few (and there's always a few....). yet when rudimentary
- or even sophisticated - technological achievements were pioneered
in the ancient world, they were discouraged. Even now, Rome's imperial
heritage is an impressive sight. Methods of moving heavy stone
around would have been our first priority in such a situation.
Yet they were vetoed at the time because they would have taken
work away from the poor, who laboured to construct those edifices.
If functional durability was our key, then the Romans would win
hands-down. So my opening gambit on interdisciplinarity is a simple
historical one: history can give a very useful sense of perspective.
Everything looks different depending on what context it is placed
in. Because Psammetichus was interested in what made a particular
people and culture the principal one of the civilised world, a
perennial concern. His evidence pointed backwards, into the mysteries
of the deep past: our evidence tends to point out and up: his Phrygian-speaking
children, our atomic bomb and space flights. The meaning of the
evidence is defined to the greatest extent by the context: without
that, they are mere curiosities.
An historical account of these factors is perhaps the easiest
option: not so easy to place these matters in a scientific context,
and not just because we are dealing with the past. We *could* recreate
those 'experiments' with children, and we might even get the same
result. The same evidence would not support the same hypothesis,
nor would have it a comparable significance. Psammetichus' science
has now become history, or possibly anthropology: it has moved
irremediably from one discipline to another.
These disciplines, or perhaps they are fields, of history and
science have very different methods for dealing with evidence.
For a start, historians have to take evidence where they can find
it; scientists can almost literally will it into existence for
the most part (or show that it is near-impossible to produce).
For the historian, there is so much that has fallen below the threshold
of visibility that we must constantly remind ourselves of the partiality
of our material. Possibly the most dramatic transition that science
has made in recent centuries (and as a classicist, I have a longer
perspective than most) has been precisely the reduction of that
threshold: visibility has proved to be negotiable, beginning with
the microscope or its forerunners. Simple glass allowed for a revolution
in knowledge.
So the circumstances of these fields are almost inverted: science
expanding exponentially, at least potentially; history, while accumulating
a larger field as every day passes, at the mercy of entropy as
ancient and medieval material in particular literally crumbles,
not least thanks to the petrochemical revolution in science. Given
the recent rise in sheer historical material as more and more information
is recorded - to the point of overwhelm - , we can probably say
that we know less and less about more and more.
Given these, and the manifold other differences between these
two areas of knowledge, can we find any common ground; can we really
talk of interdisciplinary understanding of how evidence is handled
or contextualised? The historian has responded to the lack of evidence
by becoming expert in interpretative flexibility: the antithesis
of the scientist, who seeks one answer within a multitude of possibilities.
Scientists, at least to my perception, like to focus on the correct
answer. So the Guardian has a weekly column called 'bad science'
where undisciplined claims are displayed in all their errors: a
similar approach to history is pretty unthinkable, at least by
most. What on earth can these two learn from one another? Or, to
put it in a more historical way, where can we stand such that a
useful perspective can be had?
One thing that I think worth stressing is the extent to which
a discipline is bound by its material: they are typically named
after the type of evidence that they touch on. So from the bottom
up, we have the interesting material, whether it be old, chemical,
biological, literary, social and so on. This is often assumed to
shape the various hypotheses that mysteriously arise from that
material: a chemist is interested in what chemical can do, for
instance. The only hindrance to this pure innocence could do is
the dreaded phrase of academia: grants and funding. In other words,
the questions that we put to the evidence come preformed to a large
extent. Thus, for instance, there is much medical research in this
country, almost purely because the Wellcome Trust can fund relatively
vast numbers of projects. Similarly, in history, the history of
medicine would not, most likely, support entire departments or
units without their money to make it possible (and I speak as a
recent beneficiary). In other areas money is virtually non-existent
and questions are therefore not asked or properly answered.
The area which I am circling with some hesitation is that of hypotheses.
There is no evidence without a hypothesis, just random facts, often
waiting to be discovered. The first context, then, of evidence
is that of the hypothesis. I often told my students to make up
their minds about the subject they were about to research, to pick
an arbitrary conclusion before they had done any reading: because
a clearly formulated hypothesis soon becomes unworkable in the
light of the material, or, if they made a lucky guess, far more
refined. Those who took the advice formulated better arguments
because they could see their evidence much more clearly than those
who simply went off and read lots of books.
But if a hypothesis bestows meaning upon evidence, where does
it in turn gain its own validity and relevance? This, I think,
is where the questions become more compelling. Hypothesis is not
an unconnected fragment of truth or falsity; it only makes sense
in an argument. But I wish to put a different spin on it by referring
not to arguments, but to narratives.
Why refer to narrative? Apart from the bonus of irritating many
by its evocation by the spectre of post-modernism (and an irritated
seminar is always more lively than one lulled by familiar platitudes)
it refers to a particular function of an argument, whether historical,
scientific, literary, mathematical and so on. I would suggest that
narrative is the whole point. As every good English school teacher
will have mentioned, a good story has a beginning, a middle and
an end. The sequential progress of a series with some kind of closure
has long been an obsession of humanity - back to the earliest writings.
You could call it the search for closure, the desire to know either
what happened, what is happening, or what will happen. Depending
on your needs, you might be an anti-narrativist, like a defence
lawyer, who wishes to create enough holes in her opponent's narrative
to render it unfit for use.
So this is my first suggestion: that one point at which all the
disciplines meet, the campfire around which they all sit, is the
appropriate completion of their narrative, the contented fulfillment
of the explanation, the conversion of the unknown to the known.
Hypothesis is the sentence not the chapter in a narrative. Psammetichus'
children proved the hypothesis that the Phrygian tongue was the
oldest, older even than the Egyptians'. That fed into a narrative
about the various nations, which could now begin accurately: the
end of the beginning as it were. The biologist who cures a little-known
cancer closes another narrative with the *right* ending: the patient
recovers. One potential field of interest is the distinguishing
in different disciplines of what constitutes closure: how tolerant
are different areas in adjusting to theories that work from the
bottom up (ie they fit with the available evidence but clash with
other, pre-existing narratives). Paul Feyerabend spent many books
and many years arguing that science had never lived up its claims
as objective. I have found in my own research that the most closely
argued position, fitting absolutely with the available evidence
like a glove, can encounter fierce resistance if it does not accord
with other narratives that intersect, like a crossword puzzle whose
answers refuse to interact. What do different disciplines do when
their narratives fail to accord?
So far then I have suggested a necessary context for evidence
- hypothesis - and a useful context for hypothesis - narrative.
There is an awful lot more that could be said about that, and hopefully
a small fraction of it will arise in the discussion. Now I want
to test your patience a little and introduce yet another contextual
level, for which I have another unsatisfactory term.
If our interest in evidence leads to hypothesis, which must then
necessarily form a relationship with a greater argument, a wider
narrative, then the same question can be put to our narrative:
at which point does it attain some kind of completion? To put it
another way, what informs the narrative, underlies its validity?
Whereas a narrative has sequence and completion, the domain upon
which it draws does not necessarily have to. Whereas a hypothesis,
a statement, makes sense in the context of the narrative (and sometimes
only the narrative, not any wider context), the narrative itself
has to conform to a wider and altogether more diffuse set of understandings
- which I will call discourse, or cultural discourse.
So even though an argument, or an experiment, might make reasonable
sense on its own terms, it may not survive within the broader discourse:
there was good evidence that the earth went round the sun long
before the broader cultural discourse permitted the idea to take
hold. The evidence led to the hypothesis, the hypothesis gave rise
to a narrative that both reflected and strengthened it, but the
story did not fit with broader expectations. Once again, we have
a check and influence on the handling of evidence, another set
of tensions and checks.
As will be obvious, this Venn diagram-type of approach to evidence
is not one-way, though many will find that they are working from
the bottom up, so to speak. Evidence will stimulate changes in
understanding that will alter discourse. This of course is the
ideal, though it is not clear to me that it is always what happens.
Different aspects of discourse will often act as a disincentive
to new ideas. For something to find its way anew into cultural
discourse it must often overcome far more serious barriers than
a minor modification. To cite an example that seems to keep cropping
up in the Leverhulme Evidence project, if one wanted to prove that
homeopathy worked, it would not be a simple question of a few studies
that indicated promising results: monumentally impressive results
would be needed, because homeopathy violates several fundamental
tenets of the cultural discourse, including the preference of materialistic,
recordable and straightforward correlations. If one wanted to argue
that vaccinations were not as useful or potent as they are claimed
to be, then one would need a similarly overwhelming amount of evidence.
I do not make these claims here, but I know of their existence
and cite them only as examples of tensions within the broader discourse.
It is those kinds of tensions that I suggest will be fruitful areas
for interdisciplinary comparison: moments where unity and seamlessness
conspicuously breaks down. I suggest that rich beginnings can be
made where the stakes are high, where much remains to be proven
and all the appropriate and inappropriate factors are in plainer
view.
It is not the evidence that can be compared, nor the methods used
to reach a hypothesis: there we will find hopelessly irreconcilable
differences. If we are to take an interdisciplinary approach to
evidence, some kind of unity and comparison can only be made at
the level where a narrative, or some conclusions, are constructed.
What are the different types of narrative? How do they draw on
broader assumptions within cultural discourse? To what extent are
they 'bottom-up' (based 'purely' on evidence) or 'top-down' (inductive
treatments of the evidence, which is moulded to fit expectations).
Every narrative has to find its place within the society that constructed
it so that the world can be represented coherently. One might reasonably
say that is the point of the exercise.
|
|
|